Thursday, July 23, 2020

Two Hundred and Thirty Six

In order to receive the right answer, we must ask the right question.  But how do we determine which kind is the right kind?

We are finite beings, and the universe is infinite—too vast for us to know the right questions to ask, let alone know when we receive the right answers.  All we can know is what’s right for us.

We all know what’s right for us.  We’re born knowing right from wrong, and that what’s right for us is right for every being like us, however much they seem to differ.  But as we grow older most of us forget, and by the time we’re adults we’re more often guided by what we call passion than what we call reason.

We pride ourselves on being the only animal that uses reason rather than relying on instinct to determine what’s right.  But we use reason seldom—usually only after we’ve acted out of passion—in order to rationalize and justify acts we realize, too late, were wrong.

The ancient Greeks defined—perhaps even invented—reason.  Apparently their model was the chain of questions and answers by which disputes were settled in their law courts.

A chain of questions and answers in a courtroom usually ends in a judgment; but while that judgment may be as near to the truth as a judge and/or jury can determine, and is usually accepted as such, it is determined more by which lawyer makes the best argument than by which is the most truthful argument.

A lawyer is not an impartial seeker of truth who follows the evidence wherever it leads.  He’s an employee, paid to present the evidence in the way most favorable to his client. He must not break the law by lying to the court, but he can bend it by misrepresenting the meaning and/or minimizing the importance of evidence unfavorable to his client.  It would be unethical for him not to, because his duty as a lawyer is to give his client the best defense he can without actually lying.  We all know this, yet we accept, or pretend to accept, the judgment of the court because the search for truth is infinite and we are finite.  We accept the judgment of the court because the alternative to public justice is private justice in which each man is a law unto himself, and we can't live together as a community if each man is a law unto himself.

We accept the judgment of the community—or rather the judgment of those we accept as representatives of the community: its judges and juries­—not because we believe they’re infallible, but because we value order more than truth.  The search for truth never ends, but order gives us immediate and tangible benefits.

The courtroom’s chain of questions and answers usually ends in some resolution, but outside the court there can be no resolution because the chain is endless.  Every answer raises new questions.  But just as the law distinguishes between minor crimes, for which the defendant can be judged guilty based a preponderance of the evidence because the consequences are minor, and major crimes, for which s/he must be found guilty beyond a reasonable doubt, so do we, when we reason, make decisions in small matters based on less information than we require when making decisions in large matters.  We demand certainty when deciding matters of life and death, just as a judge requires proof beyond a reasonable doubt to find someone guilty of murder.

But reason is as imperfect a tool for determining the truth as law is for determining right from wrong.

It’s a rule among lawyers that a lawyer never asks a question of a witness unless he already knows the answer.  Similarly, when we reason, every question we ask assumes we already know the answer to a previous question.  If we ask "Does god exist?", we assume we already know the answer to at least one question about the nature of god: we know that if s/he/it exists, s/he/it exists as one god, not many.  The question "Does god exist?" therefore resembles "Have you stopped beating your wife?" the lawyers’ classic example of a question that can’t be answered because it assumes the answer to a previous question: "Do you beat your wife?"  Every question we ask assumes we know the answer(s) to previous question(s)—answers which may be wrong—so we can never be sure we’re asking the right question.

If the universe is infinite and we are finite, the search for truth is endless and we can never know enough to know which question to ask.  All we can know of the universe is that small part of it that is ours, so the only question we should ask of it is what’s right for us.

Those who seem to us wise accept that we are finite parts of an infinite universe too vast for us to ever know it, so it’s foolish to try.  But the wise are a minority.  Most of us see ourselves as separate not only from the whole of which the wise believe we’re a part, but separate from each other as well.

Our first mistake—our original sin­—was to split the whole into parts—usually two, the first and simplest division.  Like Marduk, who kills Tiamat, his mother, and splits her body into two parts which become heaven and earth, so have we split our world into two parts consisting of the rulers and the ruled.

Our ancestors could not deal with the apparent paradox that each of us is a unique individual, yet all of us are alike in being parts of a greater whole, so they split themselves in two; and those two then turned against each other in a battle to determine which would rule and which would be ruled.  But because we are all parts of the whole, in turning against each other we turned against that whole; and against ourselves as well.

But what if the universe of which we are a part is not the whole?

Those we call mystics believe we're finite parts of an infinite whole which we can no more understand than a cell can understand the body of which it is a part.  We should therefore love each other as we love ourselves, because we need each other to be complete.  But those we call religious believe the the universe is not whole, but split between the natural and the supernatural.

Gods are not a part of the mystic’s belief that all is one. They're part of the religious belief that the universe is split into two parts: masters, whether natural or supernatural, and their slaves. The attitude we take towards others can therefore be that of a slave towards its master, whether human or divine, or that of a master­—stern but just, or kind and loving, but always superior to its slavenever the attitude that however different we appear to be, both of us are, at some level and in some way, equals. This leads us to the delusion that one of us is superior to the other not only in some way, but in every way.  One of us is good, and the other evil.  Or only one of us is real, and the other merely an imitationor even worse, an illusion.

The belief that the universe is split into two worlds, only one of which is real and the other an illusion, is one we associate with religion even though it's older than what we call religion, and not exclusive to it.  Most educated people claim they no longer believe in religion, and now believe in science; but they still believe the universe is split.  Scientists and the religious differ only in how they believe it's split.  Scientists say mathematics is more real than the material world we perceive with our senses, just as the world of ideal forms was the real world for Plato.

Unlike mystics, both scientists and the religious also believe the universe is knowable.  Scientists claim their method of questioning the universe will eventually enable us to know if not everything about it, certainly everything worth knowing—what can't be quantified isn't worth knowingwhile the religious claim they already know everything they need to know about it thanks to the revelation of a god delivered through one of his prophets.  But what was once dogma for both scientists and the religious—that the universe is knowable because it is uniformly the same everywhere in all directions, therefore to know a part is to know the whole—is now being questioned.  Beyond a certain point our telescopes can detect no stars, so our universe has a boundary, and is expanding into what appears to be a void.  But in that void there may be other universes we can't see.

A finite universe is knowable, in theory if not in practice—but a void may contain other universes so distant from ours that we will never know them, confirming the mystic’s view that reality is infinite and therefore unknowable by us finite beings.

 Does any of this matter?

I’ve always written only for myself, but now nothing I write matters to me, so it matters to no one.

We are social animals.  A man must be either a god or a beast to live as I do, without the companionship of his own kind—or worse, a beast who imagines himself a god.  I’ve never made that mistake, but I did once make the mistake of believing, or allowing others to fool me into believing, that I was, or could be, their savior.  Perhaps I have helped some, but I saved no one.  They didn’t need to be saved because they weren’t lost.  And yet they are lost, because they believe they are.

They believe there’s only one way to live, but they can’t or won’t live that way any longer, and they can’t or won’t find another way; so they’re lost, with no Virgil to guide them through this hell of their own making.  Their only companion is a Mephistopheles whom they, like Faust, called up not to lead them out of hell, but into it.         

No comments:

Post a Comment